Thatâs a rich seam to mine, Lloyd â one that links cyberneticsâ formative years to exactly the kind of philosophical territory Godfrey-Smith is hinting at.
Historical backdrop: teleologyâs exile and its return
- Classical teleology: Aristotleâs final causes (things have intrinsic purposes â acorns âaimâ to become oak trees).
- Mechanistic banishment: 17thâ18th century science, especially Newtonian mechanics, sought to expel purpose-talk from natural philosophy, treating phenomena as matter-in-motion under impersonal laws.
- Darwinâs selective revival: Darwinâs natural selection reintroduced purpose-like language â eyes for seeing â but grounded it in a blind, non-intentional process. This is what philosophers call âteleonomyâ: function without foresight.
The teleological pivot in cybernetics (1940sâ60s)
Cybernetics arose in a moment when âpurposeâ became safe again in scientific discourse â not as metaphysics, but as control and feedback.
- Norbert Wiener & the Macy Conferences: In Cybernetics (1948), Wiener framed purposiveness as a behavioral pattern definable in terms of goal-directed feedback loops.
- Ross Ashbyâs âhomeostatâ: Ashbyâs adaptive machine could shift internal parameters to maintain stability â a mechanical analogue of âseeking a goal.â Purpose wasnât mystical; it was negative feedback acting against perturbation.
- Rosenblueth, Wiener, and Bigelow (1943): Their paper âBehavior, Purpose, and Teleologyâ was pivotal â arguing that âpurposeful behaviorâ could be defined as behavior directed toward the attainment of a goal, measurable in terms of the systemâs output trajectory relative to that goal.
- Key move: make purpose an operational concept â no need to assume conscious intention.
- They distinguished: random, purposeful, teleological, and extrapolatory behavior.
- Claude Shannon & information theory: Although not overtly teleological, Shannonâs framework dovetailed with cyberneticsâ goal-oriented communication models (minimizing uncertainty toward a target message).
- Grey Walterâs tortoises: Simple robots with phototaxis (light-seeking) and self-charging behavior. The public saw them as âaliveâ because they seemed to want to survive.
Teleology reframed as teleonomy
Cyberneticians replaced Aristotelian âfinal causeâ with feedback-defined goals:
- In engineering: thermostat âwantsâ to keep temperature at 22°C.
- In biology: organism âseeksâ homeostasis.
- The word teleonomy gained traction in the 1960s (e.g., Ernst Mayr in biology) to describe systems whose apparent purposefulness is fully explainable by physical laws + feedback + selection history.
Why it mattered
- It re-legitimized purpose-language in science without metaphysical baggage.
- In AI precursors, it enabled the idea that machines could âhave goalsâ in a strictly behavioral sense.
- In philosophy of mind, it blurred the line between living and mechanical systems â making possible later discussions about machine intentionality.
Resonance with todayâs AI
- Modern reinforcement learning, control theory, and even large language models can be analyzed in teleonomic terms: optimization toward a goal state in a dynamic environment.
- The cyberneticiansâ move â defining purpose in purely functional, feedback-driven terms â is the ancestor of how AI research today talks about âobjectivesâ without assuming inner sentience.
If you like, I can reconstruct the 1943 RosenbluethâWienerâBigelow taxonomy in its original form, because itâs almost a Rosetta Stone for how âpurposeâ was smuggled back into the scientific lexicon without breaking the mechanistic taboo. Itâs surprisingly poetic in its sparseness. |